Both were materialistic, denying
categorically the existence of any spiritual substances; even divine beings and
the soul were declared to be formed of matter. In Stoicism and Epicureanism
alike there were definite traces of defeatism, since
both of them implied that the efforts of man are futile and suggested a
retreat into Oriental quietism as an aim for the wise to pursue. Lastly, the two
philosophies were similar in their doctrines that concepts and abstractions are
nothing but names, that only particular things are real, and that all knowledge
has its basis in sense perception.
But in many ways the two systems were quite different. Zeno and
his principal disciples taught that the cosmos is an ordered whole in which all
contradictions are resolved for ultimate good. Evil is, therefore, relative; the
particular misfortunes which befall human beings are but necessary incidents to
the final perfection of the universe. Everything that happens is rigidly
determined in accordance with rational purpose. Man is not master of his fate;
his destiny is a link in an unbroken chain. He is free only in the sense that he
can accept his fate or rebel against it. But whether he accepts or rebels, he
cannot overcome it. The supreme duty of man is to submit to the order of the
universe in the knowledge that that order is good; in other words, to resign
himself as graciously as possible to his fate. Through such an act of
resignation he will attain to the highest happiness, which consists in tranquillity of mind. The individual who is most truly happy is therefore the
man who by the assertion of his rational nature has accomplished a perfect
adjustment of his life to the cosmic purpose and has purged his soul of all
bitterness and whining protest against evil turns of fortune.
The Stoics developed an ethical and social theory which accorded
well with their general philosophy described above. Believing that the highest
good consists in serenity of mind, they naturally emphasized duty and
self-discipline as cardinal virtues. Recognizing the prevalence of particular
evil, they taught that men should be tolerant and forgiving in their attitudes
toward one another. They denied racial exclusiveness and held that all men are
brothers under the fatherhood of one God. Unlike their contemporaries, the
Cynics, they did not recommend that man should withdraw from society but urged
participation in public affairs as a duty for the citizen of rational mind. They
condemned slavery and war, but it was far from their purpose to preach any
crusade against these evils. They were disposed to think that the results which
would flow from violent measures of social change would be worse than the
diseases they were supposed to cure. Besides, what difference did it make that
the body should be in bondage so long as the mind was free? Despite its negative
character the Stoic philosophy was the noblest product of the Hellenistic Age.
Its equalitarianism, pacifism, and humanitarianism were important factors in
mitigating the harshness not only of that time but of later centuries as well.
Whereas the Stoics went back to Heracletus for much of their
conception of the universe, the Epicureans derived their metaphysics chiefly
from Democritus. Epicurus taught that the basic ingredients of all things are
minute, indivisible atoms, and that change and growth are the results of the
combination and separation of these particles. Nevertheless, while accepting the
materialism of the atomists, Epicurus rejected their absolute mechanism. He
denied that an automatic, mechanical motion of the atoms can be the cause of
all things in the universe. Though he admitted that the atoms move downward in
perpendicular lines because of their weight, he insisted upon endowing them
with a spontaneous ability to swerve from the perpendicular and thereby to
combine with one another. The chief reason for this peculiar modification of
the atomic theory was to make possible a belief in human freedom. If the atoms
were capable only of mechanical motion, then man, who is made up of atoms, would
be reduced to the status of an automaton; and fatalism would be the law of the
universe. In this repudiation of the mechanistic interpretation of life,
Epicurus was probably closer to the Hellenic spirit than either Democritus or
the Stoics.
The ethical philosophy of the Epicureans was based upon the
doctrine that the highest good for man is pleasure. But they did not include
all forms of indulgence in the category of genuine pleasure. The so-called
pleasures of the debauched man should be avoided, since every excess of
carnality must be balanced by its portion of pain. On the other hand, a moderate
satisfaction of bodily appetites is permissible and may be regarded as a good in
itself. Better than this is mental pleasure, sober contemplation of the reasons
for the choice of some things and the avoidance of others, and mature
reflection upon satisfactions previously enjoyed. The highest of all pleasures, however, consists in serenity of soul, in the complete
absence of both mental and physical pain. This end can be best achieved through
the elimination of fear, especially fear of the supernatural, since that is the
sovereign source of mental pain. Man must recognize from the study of philosophy
that the soul is material and therefore cannot survive the body, that the
universe operates of itself, and that the gods do not intervene in human
affairs. The gods live remote from the world and are too intent upon their own
happiness to bother about what takes place on earth. Since they do not reward or
punish men either in this life or in a life to come, there is no reason why they
should be feared. The Epicureans thus came by a different route to the same
general conclusion as the Stoics—the supreme good is tranquillity of mind.
The ethics of the Epicureans as well as their political theory
rested squarely upon a utilitarian basis. In contrast with the Stoics, they did
not insist upon virtue as an end in itself but taught that the only reason why
man should be good is to increase his own happiness. In like manner, they denied
that there is any such thing as absolute justice; laws and institutions are just
only in so far as they contribute to the welfare of the individual. Certain
rules have been found necessary in every complex society for the maintenance of
security and order. Men obey these rules solely because it is to their advantage
to do so. Thus the origin and existence of the state are rooted directly in
self-interest. Generally speaking, Epicurus held no high regard for either
political or social life. He considered the state as a mere convenience and
taught that the wise man should take no active part in public life. Unlike the
Cynics, he did not propose that man should abandon civilization and return to
nature; yet his conception of the happiest life was essentially passive and
defeatist. The wise man will recognize that he cannot eradicate the evils in the
world no matter how strenuous and intelligent his efforts; he will therefore
withdraw to "cultivate his garden,"study philosophy, and enjoy the fellowship
of a few congenial friends.
A more radically defeatist philosophy was that propounded by the
Skeptics. Although Skepticism was founded by Pyrrho, a contemporary of Zeno and
Epicurus, it did not reach the zenith of its popularity until about a century
later under the influence of Carneades (214-129 B.C.). The chief source of
inspiration of the Skeptics was the Sophist teaching that all knowledge is
derived from sense perception and therefore must be limited and relative. From
this they deduced the conclusion that we cannot prove anything. Since the
impressions of our senses deceive us, no truth can be certain. All we can say is
that things appear to be such and such; we do not know what they really
are. We have no definite knowledge of the supernatural, of the meaning of
life, or even of right and wrong. It follows that the sensible course to pursue
is suspension of judgment; this alone can lead to happiness. If man will abandon
the fruitless quest for absolute truth and cease worrying about good and evil,
he will attain that equanimity of mind which is the highest satisfaction that
life affords. The Skeptics were even less concerned than the Epicureans with
political and social problems. Their ideal was the typically Hellenistic one of
escape for the individual from a world he could neither understand nor reform.
Hellenistic thought reached its lowest point in the philosophies
of Philo Judaeus and the Neo-Pythagoreans in the last century
b.c. and the first century
a.d. The proponents of the two
systems were in general agreement as to their basic teachings, especially in
their predominantly religious viewpoint. They believed in a transcendent God so
far removed from the world as to be utterly unknowable to mortal minds. They
conceived the universe as being sharply divided between spirit and matter. They
considered everything physical and material as evil; man's soul is imprisoned in
his body, from which an escape can be effected only through rigorous denial and
mortification of the flesh. Their attitude was mystical and anti-intellectual:
truth comes neither from science nor from reason but from revelation; the
feeble deductions of the human mind are worthy of nothing but contempt; the
ultimate aim in life is to accomplish a mystic union with God, to lose one's
self in the divine.
Hellenistic literature is significant mainly for the light which
it throws upon the character of the civilization. Most of the writings showed
little originality or depth of thought. But they poured forth from the hands of
the copyists in a profusion that is almost incredible when we consider that the
art of printing by movable type was unknown. The names of at least i ioo
authors have been discovered already, and more are being added from year to
year. Much of what they wrote was trash, comparable to the Sunday supplements
and cheap novels of our own day. Nevertheless, there were several works of more
than mediocre quality and a few which met the highest standards ever set by the
Greeks.
The leading types of Hellenistic poetry were the drama, the
pastoral, and the mime. Drama was almost exclusively comedy, represented mainly
by the plays of Menander. His plays were entirely different from the comedy of
Aristophanes. They were distinguished by naturalism rather than by satire, by
preoccupation with the seamy side of life rather than with political or
intellectual issues. Their dominant theme was romantic love, with its pains and
pleasures, its intrigues and seductions, and its culmination in happy marriage.
The greatest author of pastorals and mimes was Theocritus of Syracuse, who wrote
in the first half of the third century b.c.
His pastorals, as the name implies, celebrate the charm of life in the
country and idealize the simple pleasures of rustic folk. The mimes, on the
other hand, portray in colorful dialogue the squabbles, ambitions, and varied
activities of the bourgeoisie in the great metropolitan cities.
The field of prose literature was dominated by the historians,
the biographers, and the authors of Utopias. By far the ablest of the writers of
history was Polybius of Megalopolis, who lived during the second century
b.c. From the standpoint of his scientific approach and his
zeal for truth, he probably deserves to be ranked second only to Thucydides
among all the historians in ancient times; but he excelled Thucydides in his
grasp of the importance of social and economic forces. Although most of the
biographies were of a light and gossipy character, their tremendous popularity
bears eloquent testimony to the literary tastes of the time. Even more
significant was the popularity of the Utopias, or descriptive accounts of ideal
states. Virtually all of them depicted a life of social and economic equality,
free from greed, oppression, and strife, on an imaginary island or in some
distant, unfamiliar region. Generally in these paradises money was considered to
be unknown, trade was prohibited, all property was held in common, and all men
were required to work with their hands in producing the necessaries of life. We
are probably justified in assuming that the profusion of this Utopian literature
was a direct result of the rottenness and injustice of Hellenistic society and a
consciousness of the need for reform.
Hellenistic art preserved only a few of the superior qualities of
the art of the Greeks. In place of the humanism, balance, and restraint which
had characterized the architecture and sculpture of the Golden Age, qualities of
exaggerated realism, sensationalism, and voluptuousness now became dominant.
The simple and dignified Doric and Ionic temples gave way to luxurious palaces,
costly mansions, and elaborate public buildings and monuments symbolical of
power and wealth. A typical example was the great lighthouse of Alexandria,
which rose to a height of nearly 400 feet, with three diminishing stories and
eight columns to support the light at the top. Sculpture likewise exhibited
tendencies in the direction of extravagance and sentimentality. Many of the
statues and figures in relief were huge and some of them almost grotesque.
Violent emotionalism and sordid realism were features common to the majority.
Among the examples of this type of sculpture may be mentioned the Laocoon
and the frieze of the Great Altar of Zeus at Pergamum with its giant gods,
ferocious animals, and hybrid monsters mingled in desperate combat to symbolize
the struggle of Greeks with Gauls. But by no means all of Hellenistic sculpture
was overwrought and grotesque. Some of it was distinguished by a calmness and
poise and compassion for human suffering reminiscent of the best work of the
great fourth-century artists. Statues which exemplify these superior qualities
include the Aphrodite of
Melos (Venus de Milo) and the Winged Victory of
Samothrace.
|